(* Buster Testacles and his infeasibly large Monad ... or is it
Testacles Monad and his infeasibly large Buster ... or is it
Monad Buster and his infeasibly large Testicles ... ?
You see, it's worth taking some trouble to get the arguments in the
right order, so that we can use currying and type-directed partial
evaluation to compose monadic representations at the same time as
we compose parsers for those types. And, if we can compose the
types, then we should be able to compose the semantics too.
There are also "fringe benefits" to be had --- decidable
Higher-Order Unification, for example. That sounds useful. ["Higher
Order Unification Revisited: Complete Sets of Transformations", by
Wayne Snyder and Jean H. Gallier] It might make HOU decidable for
any language we interpret in a monad. If so, then that ought to
make quite a lot of stuff decidable. Peano Arithmetic (PA) for
example. Then Ladies will be able to understand the proofs in the
Arithmetica of Diophantus.
The Arithmetica of Diophantus was written by a Woman. The reason I
think I know this is that little men, e.g. Heath, don't seem to
understand it. I know this because Heath asserts as a fact, some
statement to the effect that ``Diophantus only used a single
variable in his problems because he couldn't conceive of the notion
"more than one variable"''. _Even though_ he observes that
Diophantus takes great pains to cast problems in two or more
unknowns into monadic form.
Heath apparently sees no reason to explain to his readers this
utterly incredible discovery he has made: which is, how it is that
the "man" who had apparently invented the notion of using a
non-numerical symbol, i.e., a _variable,_ to represent an unknown,
and who had proved dozens and dozens of theorems in arithmetic and
whose examples frequently used six digit numbers, couldn't
_conceive_ of the notion of "one variable" generalisng to "two
variables" or "three variables".
Heath thus seems to think Diophantus stupid. Yet Heath knows at the
same time that he (Heath, I mean!) doesn't know how Diophantus
proved "the porisms" which are referred to throughout the text. It
doesn't seem to occur to Heath that the author might have had a
_reason_ for not using more than one unknown value in the
equations, and that that reason might have something to do with the
unknown (to Heath) proof methods in the porisms. Maybe the machine,
"for technical reasons", couldn't automatically generate proofs for
propositions with more than one hypothetical?
This is what I see as typical of how little men treat the thought
of Women when it is so far advanced of their own that they cannot
even recognise it as thought. They are at best patronising (see
e.g. Babbage's comments on the work of Ada Augusta Lovelace), or
they ridicule it. Perhaps that's better than them recognising that
it _is_ thought, but not being able to understand it, because then
they get angry and all they can think of doing is trying to insult
her.
Now if there is any reader who is scoffing "... and of course both
Diophantus and Heath would have been completely familiar with
Eilenberg and Moore, not to mention Moggi!" Well, I won't complain.
At least you're not insulting me. But if you want to learn
something, perhaps for the first time in your life, then look up
what Aristotle writes on the theory of proportionals, in particular
on the proposition Proportionals Alternate (PA) which is Euclid's
Prop. V.16. It seems to be about using translations between
languages to apply the same proof in three different domains:
logic, arithmetic and geometry.
But I have to agree with Wadler on one thing: I'm also a fan of
John Reynolds. What I love about the man is that he writes to
explain things, not just because he thinks he can make himself look
clever. And he doesn't make himself look clever, because he
explains things so well that he makes what he's writing about seem
utterly trivial. Perhaps that's why so few seem to have heard of
him, and also why hardly anyone seems to have really read anything
he's written.
This is a bit of a problem, because it's _systemic_. There's a
mechanism in "academia" which consistently acts against anyone who
thinks and writes clearly, and that means _anyone_ who does work of
any real lasting value. As Leonard Cohen never dared to say,
everybody knows that the mediocre is the enemy of the best, but how
can they know that, really, when even the mediocre is perpetually
swamped by the utterly useless?
It doesn't take an academic "genius" to explain what is the
mechanism either. The problem is _trade_. Human reason is not a
least-fixedpoint, so it's not effective reason: it's co-effective
reason, and a greatest-fixedpoint. So actual Human knowledge is
inherently, necessarily, co-operative. Therefore, if you take
people whose responsibility is the acquisition and dissemination of
knowledge, and you force them to compete against each other in "the
race whose prize is `Daily Bread'" then they are unable to
co-operate without losing "the prize". Consequently, the good ones,
who co-operate, and who actually know something, drop out, and the
winners are ... can you guess?
Well, by a truly remarkable co-incidence, they all turn out to be
men who don't have time to read what other men write because
they're far too busy writing things for those other men to not read
... Now how long can this sort of thing go on before somebody
cottons on to the fact that what's being published is, well, less
than mediocre, shall we say? And what's going to happen then? I
daresay there are a lot of very clever schemes that have been
thought up to deal with it, so we needn't worry about anything,
need we ...?
*)
signature Monad =
sig
type 'a M
val unit : ('a -> 'b) -> 'a -> 'b M
val bind : 'a M -> ('a -> 'b M) -> 'b M
val show : ('a -> 'b) -> 'a M -> 'b
end
signature Interpreter =
sig
type term
type result
val eval : term -> result
end
signature Value =
sig
type value
type result
val showval : value -> result
val errval : string * string -> value
end
signature Evaluator =
sig
type environment
type term
type value
type 'a M
val interp : term -> environment -> value M
end
signature Environment =
sig
eqtype name
type value
type environment
val lookup : environment -> name -> value
val bind : environment -> name * value -> environment
val null : environment
end
functor ListEnvironment
(eqtype name
type value
val error : name -> value)
:> Environment
where type name = name
and type value = value =
struct
type name = name
type value = value
type environment = (name * value) list
local fun lookup e n =
case List.find (fn (n',_) => n' = n) e
of NONE => error n
| SOME (_,v) => v
fun bind e p = p::e
in
val lookup : environment -> name -> value =
lookup
val bind : environment -> name * value -> environment =
bind
val null = []
end
end
structure InterpI =
struct
type name = string
structure MonadI :> Monad =
struct (* This way you see more clearly that the Monad is just a type function *)
type 'a M = 'a
val unit : ('a -> 'b) -> 'a -> 'b M
= fn f => fn x => f x
val bind : 'a M -> ('a -> 'b M) -> 'b M
= fn x => fn f => f x
val show : ('a -> 'b) -> 'a M -> 'b
= fn f => fn x => f x
end
datatype value =
Wrong
| Num of int
| Fun of value -> value MonadI.M
datatype term =
Var of name
| Con of int
| Add of term * term
| Lam of name * term
| App of term * term
structure Value
:> Value
where type value = value
and type result = string =
struct
local
fun showval Wrong = "<wrong>"
| showval (Num i) = Int.toString i
| showval (Fun _) = "<fn>"
fun errval (_,_) = Wrong
in
type value = value
type result = string
val showval : value -> result =
showval
val errval : string * string -> value =
errval
end
end
structure Env : Environment =
ListEnvironment (type name = name
type value = Value.value
val error : name -> value =
fn n => Value.errval ("bind",n))
structure Evaluator
:> Evaluator
where type value = value
and type 'a M = 'a MonadI.M
and type environment = Env.environment
and type term = term =
struct
type environment = Env.environment
type term = term
type value = value
type 'a M = 'a MonadI.M
local
open MonadI
fun add (Num i) (Num j) = Num (i + j)
| add _ _ = Value.errval ("Add","wrong type(s)")
fun app (Fun k) a = k a
| app _ _ = unit Value.errval ("App","wrong type")
fun interp (Var x) e = unit (Env.lookup e) x
| interp (Con i) e = unit Num i
| interp (Add (u,v)) e =
bind (interp u e) (fn a =>
bind (interp v e) (fn b =>
unit (add a) b))
| interp (Lam (x,v)) e =
unit Fun (fn a =>
interp v (Env.bind e (x,a)))
| interp (App (u,v)) e =
bind (interp u e) (fn a =>
bind (interp v e) (fn b =>
app a b))
in
val interp : term -> environment -> value M
= interp
end
end
fun eval t =
let val env = Env.null
val m = Evaluator.interp t env
in MonadI.show Value.showval m
end
end
(* Wadler calls this "the standard meta-circular
interpreter". But Reynolds, who coined the phrase, might
not agree, because this interpreter doesn't
interpret itself. This is because it doesn't
represent the abstract syntax and deconstruct it.
It might be argued that this is merely a nicety, but
consider the questions Wadler asks, such as "How do we
compose interpreters in a monad?" And "Can we interpret
a call-by-need interpreter in a monad?" If the
interpreters really were meta-circular then the answers
to these questions would obviously be positive.
And Wadlers interpreters aren't modular, as he
claims. They're all one big amorphous blob.
If you now go and carefully read Reynolds' paper
"Definitional Interpreters for Higher-Order Programming
Languages" in Higher-Order and Symbolic Computation, 11,
363–397 (1998), you will see that the treatment he
gives there is far, far superior to the one Wadler
gives, some twenty years later.
Note, for example, how Reynolds uses recursive symbolic
_environments_ to implement fixedpoint combinators, and
how they dissolve in the first-order translation (p.
381). The resulting first-order meta-circular
interpreter is one of the most beautiful 20 lines of
code I've ever seen: it is just three lambda
expressions (excluding the trivial wrapper function
interpret) and one pair of these---eval and apply---are
mutually recursive. The function eval also calls the
function get, which is (simply) recursive. One final
interesting point to note is that eval takes _two_
arguments: a value, and an environment, which is a kind
of _state._
If anyone can show me more recent work that uses this
idea, with or without attribution, I would be very
interested to hear about it. I have never come across
the idea mentioned anywhere else, and it is what a
mathematician might call "highly non-obvious".
Another notable feature of Reynolds' treatment is that
he uses abstract syntax as an informal type
discipline. All the values used in definitional
interpreters are for all practical purposes,
typed. This is from "Definitional Interpreters
Revisited" in Higher-Order and Symbolic Computation,
11, 355–361 (1998):
In “Definitional Interpretersâ€, however, closures do
not contain lambda expressions, but merely unique
tags that are in one-to-one correspondence with
occurrences of lambda expressions in the program
being defunctionalized. The computations described
by these occurrences are moved to interpretive
functions associated with the points where closures
are applied to arguments. Moreover, within each
interpretive function the case selection on tags of
closures is limited to those tags that might be seen
at the point of application
. I’ve been told that this was an early example of
control flow analysis in a functional setting, which
has inspired some of the extensive development of
this area [23]. In fact, however, the limiting of
the case selections was not determined by control
flow analysis, but by the informal abstract type
declarations (called abstract syntax equations) that
guided the construction of the original interpreter.
Something which any reader of the full paper will find
curious is the fact that Reynolds' for some reason
implements the successor function and the equality
relation as bound values in the first four
interpreters, even though none of the interpreters
actually use these functions. The answer is perhaps
that in the last interpreter, which implements
memories: which are essentially lists of references,
the successor and equality are the only two primitive
constants that are needed, And coincidentally this is
also enough to bootstrap PA.
So why would anyone want to implement the last
interpreter in the first one? Perhaps because the first
one can be implemented pretty easily in any language.
And that leads to the question "Why would anyone want
memories in the first interpreter?" Well, memories are
essentially lists of references to values
(cf. Reynold's comment quoted above, regarding how
closures are implemented, and the role of abstract
syntax as an informal type discipline). So memories
allow one to implement abstract syntax in the
interpreter. And that, I think, is why the first
interpreter is called meta-circular: because it can
interpret the last interpreter, which can interpret the
first one. So those first 20 lines of code are enough
to bootstrap any language which can be described by a
grammar, i.e. in terms of abstract syntax equations on
records, and a formal semantics described in terms of
untyped lambda calculus.
That would make quite a neat API for the LLVM JIT
engine, wouldn't it? There's not much that one would
have to write ad-hoc, and then from any scripting
language, one could interpret interpreters with a
full-on assembler, capable of optimising tail-recursive
calls, and handling and throwing exceptions, and all
this running in native machine code on half a dozen
different processor architectures. And an API like that
would be an awful lot easier to use than all that macho
hairy stuff with templates and abstract classes and
what-not. Are there _really_ no simpler ways to
implement abstract syntax in c++?
Now if we have memories representing abstract syntax,
then we have (informally) typed values, one of which is
the type of memories. And those memories can hold any
sort of object that could be described by a recursive
set of abstract syntax equations.
Now take a look at the type system that MacQueen,
Plotkin and Sethi describe in "An ideal model for
recursive polymorphic types" (1983) The ideal model is
just such a set of recursive equations. Note that they
define a least-fixedpoint type variable binder, and a
pair of rules that can be included in a type inference
algorithm W, with a circular unification algorithm. As
MacQueen et al. point out, type checking is undecidable
in general, but this can be used in practice, and the
denotational semantics handle the possibility, because
there is the error value W for _dynamic_ type errors. So
much for mu, the least fixedpoint. There is also the
type nu, of type environments, which are functions from
variables to ... well, memory values, I suppose. Like
the algorithm W would be, implemented meta-circularly:
a function from lambda expressions to memory values,
i.e. abstract syntax representing types.
Now look at the 1982 paper "Principal Typeschemes for
Functional Programs" by Damas and Milner, and see the
curious comment they make in the section describing the
denotational semantics, to the effect that "A free type
variable is implicitly universally quantified across
the _whole_ of the expression in which it appears, and
so it is sufficient to verify just the instantiation of
type variables by any monotype ... " The whole
expression in this case includes the "modelled by"
turnstile, so they seem to be referring to some sort of
inner model of the type system ... one that could be
described in terms of memories, perhaps?
And since untyped lambda expressions can be represented
by abstract syntax, and since the successor and an
equality predicate can be implemented in untyped lambda
calculus, there you have it: operational semantics from
hot aehr! (This Aristotle's term, meaning
"information", as far as I can tell.)
Which brings us to "Proofs and Bloody Types" by Girard
et al. Perhaps the missing intuition (all of it is
missing, from that book!) is to be found in this
"operational denotational semantics" idea. Look perhaps
at their "denotational" model of system-T expressions
as untyped lambda expressions implemented as an
operator algebra and written in the language of ZF set
theory, then at their reducibility proofs for System F,
and then at the proofs in MacQueen et al. on the
contractive/non-expansiveness of the type operators
when they are under least-fixedpoints: these have an
eerie familiarity (so much so that it makes me feel bit
sick to think about it, but I hope that I'll soon be
able to face opening that book again, and enjoying it
--- once I have some idea what it's about.)
*)
local
open InterpI
val term0 = (App (Lam ("x", Add (Var "x", Var "x")),
Add (Con 10, Con 11)))
in
val rI = eval term0
end
Friday 30 January 2015
Tuesday 27 January 2015
Representing Data
This is what was really the idea behind Red October a general data representation for any interpreted language. It includes a section on some potentially interesting applications to cryptography, and an explanation on pages 14-15 as to why I am not yet convinced of any claims that the security of any cryptographic protocol is based on mathematics.
https://drive.google.com/file/d/0B9MgWvi9mywhX0tlbldHSjYzR0NkWGMwaGxPeVlTWVpLdkg0/view?usp=sharing
Tuesday 13 January 2015
Process Synchronisation by Communication
This is about using inter-process communication to implement process synchronisation primitives which can be used in distributed multi-programming systems: computation "in the cloud" where the particular machines which carry out the steps of a computation are nondeterministically chosen as the computation progresses. Computation distributed in this way is secure, because no one physical system has a complete representation of the state of the computation.
https://drive.google.com/file/d/0B9MgWvi9mywhN01WTHF2RmpTOWtGYlR4VjdQaWhEQlBFWHJN/view?usp=sharing
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)